Skip to content

Time Preferences

Most non-trivial economic choices involve

  1. Determine tradeoffs between costs and benefits that occur across time points
  2. Determine values (utility) of costs and benefits, by weighing costs & benefits against each other

Present Bias

Humans have a tendency to put more weight into the present rather than the future when making decision

Indifference Curves

At any point on the curve, the combination of the two will leave the consumer equally well off or equally satisfied—hence indifferent.

Shows various combinations of __ that consumers can choose
Goods-Indifference Curve two commodities at the same time point Marginal rate of substitution
Fisher’s Time-Indifference Curve same commodity at different time points time_indifference_curve

Utility Function

\[ \begin{aligned} \max U_t &= \sum_{t = 0}^\infty D(t) \cdot u_{t_0 + t} \\ u_t &= u(c_t, l_t, \dots) \end{aligned} \]

where

\(u_t\) Instantaneous utility Captures how person feels at a specific moment
Function of consumption, leisure
\(U_t\) Discounted utility Captures total utility obtained until a specific moment
\(D(t)\) Discount Function Specifies weights on utility derived in \(t\) time periods
Measures how utility in alter periods is discounted relative to earlier periods
Replaces complex psychology of how people think about future
Usually \(\in (0, 1]\)
\(\rho(t)\) Discount Rate Rate of decline in the discount function
Specifies rate at which value of \(u\) declines with delay
\(\dfrac{-D'(t)}{D(t)}\)

Standard Utility Models

Samuelson’s Exponential Quasi-Hyperbolic
Non-graphical model of Fisher’s Time-Indifference Curve
Developed as a simple approximation as a first start, not meant to be accurate
\(D(t)\) \(\delta^t\)
\(\delta \in [0, 1]\)
\(\beta \delta^t\)
\(\delta \to 1 \ (0.\bar{9})\)
\(\beta \in [0, 1]\)
\(\rho(t)\) \(- \log \vert \delta \vert \approx 1-\delta\)
Advantages Not affected by awareness issue - Separate short & long-run discounting
- Great patience for tradeoffs in the future than for tradeoff in present
- Deals with preference reversals
Limitation Constant discount rate

1. Short vs Long-Run impatience
2. Preference reversals
3. Commitment devices
Affected by awareness issue

image-20240212112607560

Estimating \(\delta\)

Ask the person the following question

What \(X\) makes you indifferent between receiving $15 today and $X at various time point \(t\)

  • \(t=1\) day
  • \(t=1\) month
  • \(t=1\) year

Assumes that utility is linear in money, ie marginal utility is constant, ie \(u(X) = X\)

IDK

Short vs Long-Run Impatience

People tend to be more patient in the long-run than in the short-run

Eg: Credit card loans

Preference Reversals

In reality, dynamic consistency is not followed. People don’t always follow through with their plans.

Hence

  • When thinking ahead to the future, we want to be patient
  • When the time actually comes, we are impatient
  • People are over-confident about their self-control

Eg: Dieting, Gym membership

Dynamic/Time Consistency

  • The action a person thinks they should take in the future always coincides with the action that they actually prefer to take once the time comes
  • A person’s preferences at different points in time are consistent with each other; there are no “intra-personal conflicts”

Commitment Devices

Arrangement taken upon by agent to restrict their future choice set, by making certain choices more costly

Demand for commitment requests (at least partial) sophistication

When you know that your future preferences will be different from present preferences, you may engage in commitment devices to penalize (and hence eliminate) few options from the future. We disapprove of the tendency for instant gratification beforehand, but struggle to actually follow through

Requirements for effectiveness of commitment device

  • Person needs to have a self-control problem: \(\beta < 1\)
  • Person needs to at least partly be sophisticated: \(\hat \beta < 1\)
  • Commitment devices needs to be effective
  • Person needs to believe that the commitment device is effective

Things that worsen effectiveness of commitment devices

  • Time-inconsistent preferences: Each time period’s self restrict set of choices for their future selves, and hence there may be difference in assessment of best action at each time period
  • Substitution: Substitution across temptation goods worsens effectiveness of commitment devices. Avoiding one temptation good may lead to increases consumption of another
  • Naivete: Person underestimates their present bias, and might
  • Naive: Not demand a helpful commitment device
  • Partial naive: Demand a unhelpful commitment device

Goods Types

Leisure Investment
Example Eating Candy Going to Gym
Finishing assignments
Quitting bad habits
Finding a job
Costs Delayed Immediate
Rewards Immediate Delayed
Result
Consumption relative to long-run
Over-consumption Under-consumption

Behavior Types

Perfect
Exponential Discounter
Naïveté Partial Naïveté Sophistication
\(\beta\) \(1\) \(< 1\) \(<1\) \(< 1\)
\(\hat \beta\)
What you think \(\beta\) is in the future
\(\beta\) \(1\) \(> \beta\)
Measures belief about future \(\beta\)
\(\beta\)
Optimism Perfect Over-optimistic
(Assumes future self will through on optimal plan)
Underestimate degree of future present bias Pessimistic
Person self-aware of preference reversal N/A
(No preference reversal)
❌ ✅ ✅
Overcommitment/
Self-control problem
❌ ❌ ✅ ❌
Set deadlines optimally ✅ ❌
(No perceived need to choose deadlines)
⚠️
(Tries, but fails)
âś…
Deadlines help Deadline not required ✅ ⚠️ ✅
Take advantage of commitment devices Not required ❌ ⚠️
(Tries, but fails)
âś…
No surprises of future present bias No present bias ❌ ❌ ✅
Overcomes short-run impatience No impatience ❌ ❌ ✅
Utility evaluation Both ways gives same result Forwards Forwards and backwards Backwards
Investment Goods: Behavior No procrastination NaĂŻve Procrastination Sophisticated Procrastination
Investment Goods: Welfare Cost 0 Large Low
Leisure Goods: Behavior No precrastination NaĂŻve precrastination Sophisticated precrastination
(self-aware about impatience, and hence consumes earlier)
Leisure Goods: Welfare Cost 0 Low Large
(does not wait until max enjoyment)

Utility Evaluation

Forward Backward
1. Start at beginning
2. Solve for optimal plan, assuming future self follows plan
3. Person takes first step in that plan
4. Go to next period
5. Go to step 2
1. Start at end
2. Solve for optimal action
3. Go back to previous period
4. Solve for optimal action, considering what happens in next period
5. Go to step 3

Example

Consider the following table showing the utilities associated with watching a movie

image-20240212122705997

Naïveté Sophistication
Utility Evaluation t=0: Plans to go at t=3, so doesn’t go
t=1: Plans to go at t=3, so doesn’t go
t=2: Goes
t=2: goes if she hasn’t
t=1: realizes she won’t wait until t=3, she goes
t=0: realizes she won’t wait until t=2 or 3, she goes
Conclusion Goes at t=2, even though she planned to go at t=3 Just goes at t=0

Indicators of Behavior Types

  • Naivete: Person mis-predicting future behavior
  • Sophistication: Person’s use of commitment devices

Uncertainties about Future

  • Present bias
  • Planning Fallacy

Planning Fallacy

Under-estimation of effort costs of tasks, leading to people always under-performing compared to original plan, even if they are aware of this.

Last Updated: 2024-05-12 ; Contributors: AhmedThahir

Comments